SAINT AUGUSTINE
THE CITY OF GOD: BOOK NINE
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Go to Book Ten
HAVING IN THE PRECEDING BOOK SHOWN THAT THE
WORSHIP OF DEMONS MUST BE ABJURED, SINCE THEY IN A THOUSAND WAYS PROCLAIM THEMSELVES TO BE
WICKED SPIRITS, AUGUSTIN IN THIS BOOK MEETS THOSE WHO ALLEGE A DISTINCTION AMONG DEMONS,
SOME BEING EVIL, WHILE OTHERS ARE GOOD; AND, HAVING EXPLODED THIS DISTINCTION, HE PROVES
THAT TO NO DEMON, BUT TO CHRIST ALONE, BELONGS THE OFFICE OF PROVIDING MEN WITH ETERNAL
BLESSEDNESS.
CHAP. 1.--THE POINT AT
WHICH THE DISCUSSION HAS ARRIVED, AND WHAT REMAINS TO BE HANDLED.
SOME have advanced the opinion that there are
both good and bad gods; but some, thinking more respectfully of the gods, have attributed
to them so much honor and praise as to preclude the supposition of any god being wicked.
But those who have maintained that there are wicked gods as well as good ones have
included the demons under the name "gods," and sometimes though more rarely,
have called the gods demons; so that they admit that Jupiter, whom they make the king and
head of all the rest, is called a demon by Homer. Those, on the other hand, who
maintain that the gods are all good, and far more excellent than the men who are justly
called good, are moved by the actions of the demons, which they can neither deny nor
impute to the gods whose goodness they affirm, to distinguish between gods and demons; so
that, whenever they find anything offensive in the deeds or sentiments by which unseen
spirits manifest their power, they believe this to proceed not from the gods, but from the
demons. At the same time they believe that, as no god can hold direct intercourse with
men, these demons hold the position of mediators, ascending with prayers, and returning
with gifts. This is the opinion of the Platonists, the ablest and most esteemed of their
philosophers, with whom we therefore chose to debate this question,--whether the worship
of a number of gods is of any service toward obtaining blessedness in the future life. And
this is the reason why, in the preceding book, we have inquired how the demons, who take
pleasure in such things as good and wise men loathe and execrate, in the sacrilegious and
immoral fictions which the poets have written not of men, but of the gods themselves, and
in the wicked and criminal violence of magical arts, can be regarded as more nearly
related and more friendly to the gods than men are, and can mediate between good men and
the good gods; and it has been demonstrated that this is absolutely impossible.
CHAP. 2.--WHETHER AMONG
THE DEMONS, INFERIOR TO THE GODS, THERE ARE ANY GOOD. SPIRITS UNDER WHOSE GUARDIANSHIP THE
HUMAN SOUL MIGHT REACH TRUE BLESSEDNESS.
This book, then, ought, according to the promise
made in the end of the preceding one, to contain a discussion, not of the difference which
exists among the gods, who, according to the Platonists, are all good, nor of the
difference between gods and demons, the former of whom they separate by a wide interval
from men, while the latter are placed intermediately between the gods and men, but of the
difference, since they make one, among the demons themselves. This we shall discuss so far
as it bears on our theme. It has been the common and usual belief that some of the demons
are bad, others good; and this opinon, whether it be that of the Platonists or any other
sect, must by no means be passed over in silence, lest some one suppose he ought to
cultivate the good demons in order that by their mediation he may be accepted by the gods,
all of whom he believes to be good, and that he may live with them after death; whereas he
would thus be ensnared in the toils of wicked spirits, and would wander far from the true
God, with whom alone, and in whom alone, the human soul, that is to say, the soul that is
rational and intellectual, is blessed.
CHAP. 3.--WHAT APULEIUS
ATTRIBUTES TO THE DEMONS, TO WHOM, THOUGH HE DOES NOT DENY THEM REASON, HE DOES NOT
ASCRIBE VIRTUE.
What, then, is the difference between good and
evil demons? For the Platonist Apuleius, in a treatise on this whole subject, while he
says a great deal about their aerial bodies, has not a word to say of the spiritual
virtues with which, if they were good, they must have been endowed. Not a word has he
said, then, of that which could give them happiness; but proof of their misery he has
given, acknowledging that their mind, by which they rank as reasonable beings, is not only
not imbued and fortified with Virtue so as to resist all unreasonable passions, but that
it is somehow agitated with tempestuous emotions, and is thus on a level with the mind of
foolish men. His own words are: "It is this class of demons the poets refer to, when,
without serious error, they feign that the gods hate and love individuals among men,
prospering and ennobling some, and opposing and distressing others. Therefore pity,
indignation, grief, joy, every human emotion is experienced by the demons, with the same
mental disturbance, and the same tide of feeling and thought. These turmoils and tempests
banish them far from the tranquility of the Celestial gods." Can there be any doubt
that in these words it is not some inferior part of their spiritual nature, but the very
mind by which the demons hold their rank as rational beings, which he says is tossed with
passion like a stormy sea? They cannot, then, be compared even to wise men, who with
undisturbed. mind resist these perturbations to which they are exposed in this life, and
from which human infirmity is never exempt, and who do not yield themselves to approve of
or perpetrate anything which might deflect them from the path of wisdom and law of
rectitude. They resemble in character, though not in bodily appearance, wicked and foolish
men. I might indeed say they are worse, inasmuch as they have grown old in iniquity, and
incorrigible by punishment. Their mind, as Apuleius says, is a sea tossed with tempest,
having no rallying point of truth or virtue in their soul from which they can resist their
turbulent and depraved emotions.
CHAP. 4.--THE OPINION OF
THE PERIPATETICS AND STOICS ABOUT MENTAL EMOTIONS.
Among the philosophers there are two opinions
about these mental emotions, which the Greeks call paqh, while
some of our own writers, as Cicero, call them perturbations, some affections, and some,
to render the Greek word more accurately, passions. Some say that even the wise man is
subject to these perturbations, though moderated and controlled by reason, which imposes
laws upon them, and so restrains them within necessary bounds. This is the opinion of the
Platonists and Aristotelians; for Aristotle was Plato's disciple, and the founder of the
Peripatetic school. But others, as the Stoics, are of opinion that the wise man is not
subject to these perturbations. But Cicero, in his book De Finibus, shows that the Stoics
are here at variance with the Platonists and Peripatetics rather in words than in reality;
for the Stoics decline to apply the term "goods" to external and bodily
advantages, because they reckon that the only good is virtue, the art of living well,
and this exists only in the mind. The other philosophers, again, use the simple and
customary phraseology, and do not scruple to call these things goods, though in comparison
of virtue, which guides our life, they are little and of small esteem. And thus it is
obvious that, whether these outward things are called goods or advantages, they are held
in the same estimation by both parties, and that in this matter the Stoics are pleasing
themselves merely with a novel phraseology. It seems, then, to me that in this question,
whether the wise man is subject to mental passions, or wholly free from them, the
controversy is one of words rather than of things; for I think that, if the reality and
not the mere sound of the words is considered, the Stoics hold precisely the same opinion
as the Platonists and Peripatetics. For, omitting for brevity's sake other proofs which I
might adduce in support of this opinion, I will state but one which I consider conclusive.
Aulus Gellius, a man of extensive erudition, and gifted with an eloquent and graceful
style, relates, in his work entitled Noctes Atticae that he once made a voyage with an
eminent Stoic philosopher; and he goes on to relate fully and with gusto what I shall
barely state, that when the ship was tossed and in danger from a violent storm, the
philosopher grew pale with terror. This was noticed by those on board, who, though
themselves threatened with death, were curious to see whether a philosopher would be
agitated like other men. When the tempest had passed over, and as soon as their security
gave them freedom to resume their talk, one of the passengers, a rich and luxurious
Asiatic, begins to banter the philosopher, and rally him because he had even become pale
with fear, while he himself had been unmoved by the impending destruction. But the
philosopher availed himself of the reply of Aristippus the Socratic, who, on finding
himself similarly bantered by a man of the same character, answered, "You had no
cause for anxiety for the soul of a profligate debauchee, but I had reason to be alarmed
for the soul of Aristippus." The rich man being thus disposed of, Aulus Gellius asked
the philosopher, in the interests of science and not to annoy him, what was the reason of
his fear? And he willing to instruct a man so zealous in the pursuit of knowledge, at once
took from his wallet a book of Epictetus the Stoic, in which doctrines were advanced
which precisely harmonized with those of Zeno and Chrysippus, the founders of the Stoical
school. Aulus Gellius says that he read in this book that the Stoics maintain that there
are certain impressions made on the soul by external objects which they call phantasiae,
and that it is not in the power of the soul to determine whether or when it shall be
invaded by these. When these impressions are made by alarming and formidable objects, it
must needs be that they move the soul even of the wise man, so that for a little he
trembles with fear, or is depressed by sadness, these impressions anticipating the work of
reason and self-control; but this does not imply that the mind accepts these evil
impressions, or approves or consents to them. For this consent is, they think, in a man's
power; there being this difference between the mind of the wise man and that of the fool,
that the fool's mind yields to these passions and consents to them, while that of the wise
man, though it cannot help being invaded by them, yet retains with unshaken firmness a
true and steady persuasion of those things which it ought rationally to desire or avoid.
This account of what Aulus Gellius relates that he read in the book of Epictetus about the
sentiments and doctrines of the Stoics I have given as well as I could, not, perhaps, with
his choice language, but with greater brevity, and, I think, with greater clearness. And
if this be true, then there is no difference, or next to none, between the opinion of the
Stoics and that of the other philosophers regarding mental passions and perturbations, for
both parties agree in maintaining that the mind and reason of the wise man are not subject
to these. And perhaps what the Stoics mean by asserting this, is that the wisdom which
characterizes the wise man is clouded by no error and sullied by no taint, but, with this
reservation that his wisdom remains undisturbed, he is exposed to the impressions which
the goods and ills of this life (or, as they prefer to call them, the advantages or
disadvantages) make upon them. For we need not say that if that philosopher had thought
nothing of those things which he thought he was forthwith to lose, life and bodily safety,
he would not have been so terrified by his danger as to betray his fear by the pallor of
his cheek. Nevertheless, he might suffer this mental disturbance, and yet maintain the
fixed persuasion that life and bodily safety, which the violence of the tempest threatened
to destroy, are not those good things which make their possessors good, as the possession
of righteousness does. But in so far as they persist that we must call them not goods but
advantages, they quarrel about words and neglect things. For what difference does it make
whether goods or advantages be the better name, while the Stoic no less than the
Peripatetic is alarmed at the prospect of losing them, and while, though they name them
differently, they hold them in like esteem? Both parties assure us that, if urged to the
commission of some immorality or crime by the threatened loss of these goods or
advantages, they would prefer to lose such things as preserve bodily comfort and security
rather than commit such things as violate righteousness. And thus the mind in which this
resolution is well grounded suffers no perturbations to prevail with it in opposition to
reason, even though they assail the weaker parts of the soul; and not only so, but it
rules over them, and, while it refuses its consent and resists them, administers a reign
of virtue. Such a character is ascribed to AEneas by Virgil when he says,
"He stands immovable by tears,
Nor tenderest words with pity hears."
CHAP. 5.--THAT THE PASSIONS WHICH ASSAIL THE
SOULS OF CHRISTIANS DO NOT SEDUCE THEM TO VICE, BUT EXERCISE THEIR VIRTUE.
We need not at present give a careful and copious
exposition of the doctrine of Scripture, the sum of Christian knowledge, regarding these
passions. It subjects the mind itself to God, that He may rule and aid it, and the
passions, again, to the mind, to moderate and bridle them, and turn them to righteous
uses. In our ethics, we do not so much inquire whether a pious soul is angry, as why he is
angry; not whether he is sad, but what is the cause of his sadness; not whether he fears,
but what he fears. For I am not aware that any right thinking person would find fault with
anger at a wrongdoer which seeks his amendment, or with sadness which intends relief to
the suffering, or with fear lest one in danger be destroyed. The Stoics, indeed, are
accustomed to condemn compassion. But how much more honorable had it been in that Stoic
we have been telling of, had he been disturbed by compassion prompting him to relieve a
fellow-creature, than to be disturbed by the fear of shipwreck! Far better and more
humane, and more consonant with pious sentiments, are the words of Cicero in praise of
Caesar, when he says, "Among your virtues none is more admirable and agreeable than
your compassion." And what is compassion but a fellow-feeling for another's
misery, which prompts us to help him if we can? And this emotion is obedient to reason,
when compassion is shown without violating right, as when the poor are relieved, or the
penitent forgiven. Cicero, who knew how to use language, did not hesitate to call this a
virtue, which the Stoics are not ashamed to reckon among the vices, although, as the book
of the eminent Stoic, Epictetus, quoting the opinions of Zeno and Chrysippus, the founders
of the school, has taught us, they admit that passions of this kind invade the soul of the
wise man, whom they would have to be free from all vice. Whence it follows that these very
passions are not judged by them to be vices, since they assail the wise man without
forcing him to act against reason and virtue; and that, therefore, the opinion of the
Peripatetics or Platonists and of the Stoics is one and the same. But, as Cicero says,
mere logomachy is the bane of these pitiful Greeks, who thirst for contention rather than
for truth. However, it may justly be asked, whether our subjection to these affections,
even while we follow virtue, is a part of the infirmity Of this life? For the holy angels
feel no anger while they punish those whom the eternal law of God consigns to punishment,
no fellow-feeling with misery while they relieve the miserable, I no fear while they aid
those who are in danger; and yet ordinary language ascribes to them also these mental
emotions, because, though they have none of our weakness, their acts resemble the actions
to which these emotions move us; and thus even God Himself is said in Scripture to be
angry, and yet without any perturbation. For this word is used of the effect of His
vengeance, not of the disturbing mental affection.
CHAP. 6.--OF THE
PASSIONS WHICH, ACCORDING TO APULEIUS, AGITATE THE DEMONS WHO APE SUPPOSED BY HIM TO
MEDIATE BETWEEN GODS AND MEN.
Deferring for the present the question about the
holy angels, let us examine the opinion of the Platonists, that the demons who mediate
between gods and men are agitated by passions. For if their mind, though exposed to their
incursion, still remained free and superior to them, Apuleius could not have said that
their hearts are tossed with passions as the sea by stormy winds. Their mind,
then,--that superior part of their soul whereby they are rational beings, and which, if it
actually exists in them, should rule and bridle the turbulent passions of the inferior
parts of the soul,--this mind of theirs, I say, is, according to the Platonist referred
to, tossed with a hurricane of passions. The mind of the demons, therefore, is subject to
the emotions of fear, anger, lust, and all similar affections. What part of them, then, is
free, and endued with wisdom, so that they are pleasing to the gods, and the fit guides of
men into purity of life, since their very highest part, being the slave of passion and
subject to vice, only makes them more intent on deceiving and seducing, in proportion to
the mental force and energy of desire they possess?
CHAP. 7.--THAT THE
PLATONISTS MAINTAIN THAT THE POETS WRONG THE GODS BY REPRESENTING THEM AS DISTRACTED BY
PARTY FEELING, TO WHICH THE DEMONS AND NOT THE GODS, ARE SUBJECT.
But if any one says that it is not of all the
demons, but only of the wicked, that the poets, not without truth, say that they violently
love or hate certain men,--for it was of them Apuleius said that they were driven about by
strong currents of emotion,--how can we accept this interpretation, when Apuleius, in the
very same connection, represents all the demons, and not only the wicked, as intermediate
between gods and men by their aerial bodies? The fiction of the poets, according to him,
consists in their making gods of demons, and giving them the names of gods, and assigning
them as allies or enemies to individual men, using this poetical license, though they
profess that the gods are very different in character from the demons, and far exalted
above them by their celestial abode and wealth of beatitude. This, I say, is the poets'
fiction, to say that these are gods who are not gods, and that, under the names of gods,
they fight among themselves about the men whom they love or hate with keen partisan
feeling. Apuleius says that this is not far from the truth, since, though they are
wrongfully called by the names of the gods, they are described in their own proper
character as demons. To this category, he says, belongs the Minerva of Homer, "who
interposed in the ranks of the Greeks to restrain Achilles." For that this was
Minerva he supposes to be poetical fiction; for he thinks that Minerva is a goddess, and
he places her among the gods whom he believes to be all good and blessed in the sublime
ethereal region, remote from intercourse with men. But that there was a demon favorable to
the Greeks and adverse to the Trojans, as another, whom the same poet mentions under the
name of Venus or Mars (gods exalted above earthly affairs in their heavenly habitations),
was the Trojans' ally and the foe of the Greeks, and that these demons fought for those
they loved against those they hated,--in all this he owned that the poets stated something
very like the truth. For they made these statements about beings to whom he ascribes the
same violent and tempestuous passions as disturb men, and who are therefore capable of
loves and hatreds not justly formed, but formed in a party spirit, as the spectators in
races or hunts take fancies and prejudices. It seems to have been the great fear of this
Platonist that the poetical fictions should be believed of the gods, and not of the demons
who bore their names.
CHAP. 8.--HOW APULEIUS
DEFINES THE GODS WHO DWELL IN HEAVEN, THE DEMONS WHO OCCUPY THE AIR, AND MEN WHO INHABIT
EARTH.
The definition which Apuleius gives of demons,
and in which he of course includes all demons, is that they are in nature animals, in soul
subject to passion, in mind reasonable, in body aerial, in duration eternal. Now in these
five qualities he has named absolutely nothing which is proper to good men and not also to
bad. For when Apuleius had spoken of the celestials first, and had then extended his
description so as to include an account of those who dwell far below on the earth, that,
after describing the two extremes of rational being, he might proceed to speak of the
intermediate demons, he says, "Men, therefore, who are endowed with the faculty of
reason and speech, whose soul is immortal and their members mortal, who have weak and
anxious spirits, dull and corruptible bodies, dissimilar characters, similar ignorance,
who are obstinate in their audacity, and persistent in their hope, whose labor is vain,
and whose fortune is ever on the wane, their race immortal, themselves perishing, each
generation replenished with creatures whose life is swift and their wisdom slow, their
death sudden and their life a wail,--these are the men who dwell on the earth." In
recounting so many qualities which belong to the large proportion of men, did he forget
that which is the property of the few when he speaks of their wisdom being slow? If this
had been omitted, this his description of the human race, so carefully elaborated, would
have been defective. And when he commended the excellence of the gods, he affirmed that
they excelled in that very blessedness to which he thinks men must attain by wisdom. And
therefore, if he had wished us to believe that some of the demons are good, he should have
inserted in his description something by which we might see that they have, in common with
the gods, some share of blessedness, or, in common with men, some wisdom. But, as it is,
he has mentioned no good quality by which the good may be distinguished from the bad. For
although he refrained from giving a full account of their wickedness, through fear of
offending, not themselves but their worshippers, for whom he was writing, yet he
sufficiently indicated to discerning readers what opinion he had of them; for only in the
one article of the eternity of their bodies does he assimilate them to the gods, all of
whom, he asserts, are good and blessed, and absolutely free from what he himself calls the
stormy passions of the demons; and as to the soul, he quite plainly affirms that they
resemble men and not the gods, and that this resemblance lies not in the possession of
wisdom, which even men can attain to, but in the perturbation of passions which sway the
foolish and wicked, but is so ruled by the good and wise that they prefer not to admit
rather than to conquer it. For if he had wished it to be understood that the demons
resembled the gods in the eternity not of their bodies but of their souls, he would
certainly have admitted men to share in this privilege, because, as a Platonist, he of
course must hold that the human soul is eternal. Accordingly, when describing this race of
living beings, he said that their souls were immortal, their members mortal. And,
consequently, if men have not eternity in common with the gods because they have mortal
bodies, demons have eternity in common with the gods because their bodies are immortal.
CHAP. 9.--WHETHER THE
INTERCESSION OF THE DEMONS CAN SECURE FOR MEN THE FRIENDSHIP OF THE CELESTIAL GODS.
How, then, can men hope for a favorable
introduction to the friendship of the gods by such mediators as these, who are, like men,
defective in that which is the better part of every living creature, viz., the soul, and
who resemble the gods only in the body, which is the inferior part? For a living creature
or animal consists of soul and body, and of these two parts the soul is undoubtedly the
better; even though vicious and weak, it is obviously better than even the soundest and
strongest body, for the greater excellence of its nature is not reduced to the level of
the body even by the pollution of vice, as gold, even when tarnished, is more precious
than the purest silver or lead. And yet these mediators, by whose interposition things
human and divine are to be harmonized, have an eternal body in common with the gods, and a
vicious soul in common with men,--as if the religion by which these demons are to unite
gods and men were a bodily, and not a spiritual matter. What wickedness, then, or
punishment has suspended these false and deceitful mediators, as it were head downwards,
so that their inferior part, their body, is linked to the gods above, and their superior
part, the soul, bound to men beneath; united to the celestial gods by the part that
serves, and miserable, together with the inhabitants of earth, by the part that rules? For
the body is the servant, as Sallust says: "We use the soul to rule, the body to
obey;" adding, "the one we have in common with the gods, the other with the
brutes." For he was here speaking of men; and they have, like the brutes, a mortal
body. These demons, whom our philosophic friends have provided for us as mediators with
the gods, may indeed say of the soul and body, the one we have in common with the gods,
the other with men; but, as I said, they are as it were suspended and bound head
downwards, having the slave, the body, in common with the gods, the master, the soul, in
common with miserable men,--their inferior part exalted, their superior part depressed.
And therefore, if any one supposes that, because they are not subject, like terrestrial
animals, to the separation of soul and body by death, they therefore resemble the gods in
their eternity, their body must not be considered a chariot of an eternal triumph, but
rather the chain of an eternal punishment.
CHAP. 10.--THAT,
ACCORDING TO PLOTINUS, MEN, WHOSE BODY IS MORTAL, ARE LESS WRETCHED THAN DEMONS, WHOSE
BODY IS ETERNAL.
Plotinus, whose memory is quite recent, enjoys
the reputation of having understood Plato better than any other of his disciples. In
speaking of human souls, he says, "The Father in compassion made their bonds
mortal;" that is to say, he considered it due to the Father's mercy that men,
having a mortal body, should not be forever confined in the misery of this life. But of
this mercy the demons have been judged unworthy, and they have received, in conjunction
with a soul subject to passions, a body not mortal like man's, but eternal. For they
should have been happier than men if they had, like men, had a mortal body, and, like the
gods, a blessed soul. And they should have been equal to men, if in conjunction with a
miserable soul they had at least received, like men, a mortal body, so that death might
have freed them from trouble, if, at least, they should have attained some degree of
piety. But, as it is, they are not only no happier than men, having, like them, a
miserable soul, they are also more wretched, being eternally bound to the body; for he
does not leave us to infer that by some progress in wisdom and piety they can become gods,
but expressly says that they are demons forever.
CHAP. 11.--OF THE OPINION OF THE PLATONISTS, THAT
THE SOULS OF MEN BECOME DEMONS WHEN DISEMBODIED.
He says, indeed, that the souls of men are
demons, and that men become Lares if they are good, Lemures or Larvae if they are bad, and
Manes if it is uncertain whether they de serve well or ill. Who does not see at a glance
that this is a mere whirlpool sucking men to moral destruction? For, however wicked men
have been, if they suppose they shall become Larvae or divine Manes, they will become the
worse the more love they have for inflicting injury; for, as the Larvae are hurtful demons
made out of wicked men, these men must suppose that after death they will be invoked with
sacrifices and divine honors that they may inflict injuries. But this question we must not
pursue. He also states that the blessed are called in Greek
<greek>eudaimones</greek>, because they are good souls, that is to say, good
demons, confirming his opinion that the souls of men are demons.
CHAP. 12.--OF THE THREE
OPPOSITE QUALITIES BY WHICH THE PLATONISTS DISTINGUISH BETWEEN THE NATURE OF MEN AND THAT
OF DEMONS.
But at present we are speaking of those beings
whom he described as being properly intermediate between gods and men, in nature animals,
in mind rational, in soul subject to passion, in body aerial, in duration eternal. When he
had distinguished the gods, whom he placed in the highest heaven, from men, whom he placed
on earth, not only by position but also by the unequal dignity of their natures, he
concluded in these words: "You have here two kinds of animals: the gods, widely
distinguished from men by sublimity of abode, perpetuity of life, perfection of nature;
for their habitations are separated by so wide an interval that there can be no intimate
communication between them, and while the vitality of the one is eternal and indefeasible,
that of the others is fading and precarious, and while the spirits of the gods are exalted
in bliss, those of men are sunk in miseries." Here I find three opposite qualities
ascribed to the extremes of being, the highest and lowest. For, after mentioning the three
qualities for which we are to admire the gods, he repeated, though in other words, the
same three as a foil to the defects of man. The three qualities are, "sublimity of
abode, perpetuity of life, perfection of nature." These he again mentioned so as to
bring out their contrasts in man's condition. As he had mentioned "sublimity of
abode," he says, "Their habitations are separated by so wide an interval;"
as he had mentioned "perpetuity of life," he says, that "while divine life
is eternal and indefeasible, human life is fading and precarious;" and as he had
mentioned "perfection of nature," he says, that "while the spirits of the
gods are exalted in bliss, those of men are sunk in miseries." These three things,
then, he predicates of the gods, exaltation, eternity, blessedness; and of man he
predicates the opposite, lowliness of habitation, mortality, misery.
CHAP. 13.--HOW THE
DEMONS CAN MEDIATE BETWEEN GODS AND MEN IF THEY HAVE NOTHING IN COMMON WITH BOTH, BEING
NEITHER BLESSED LIKE THE GODS, NOR MISERABLE LIKE MEN.
If, now, we endeavor to find between these
opposites the mean occupied by the demons, there can be no question as to their local
position; for, between the highest and lowest place, there is a place which is rightly
considered and called the middle place. The other two qualities remain, and to them we
must give greater care, that we may see whether they are altogether foreign to the demons,
or how they are so bestowed upon them without infringing upon their mediate position. We
may dismiss the idea that they are foreign to them. For we cannot say that the demons,
being rational animals, are neither blessed nor wretched, as we say of the beasts and
plants, which are void of feeling and reason, or as we say of the middle place, that it is
neither the highest nor the lowest. The demons, being rational, must be either miserable
or blessed. And, in like manner, we cannot say that they are neither mortal nor immortal;
for all living things either live eternally or end life in death. Our author, besides,
stated that the demons are eternal. What remains for us to suppose, then, but that these
mediate beings are assimilated to the gods in one of the two remaining qualities, and to
men in the other? For if they received both from above, or both from beneath, they should
no longer be mediate, but either rise to the gods above, or sink to men beneath.
Therefore, as it has been demonstrated that they must possess these two qualities, they
will hold their middle place if they receive one from each party. Consequently, as they
cannot receive their eternity from beneath, because it is not there to receive, they must
get it from above; and accordingly they have no choice but to complete their mediate
position by accepting misery from men.
According to the Platonists, then, the gods, who
occupy the highest place, enjoy eternal blessedness, or blessed eternity; men, who occupy
the lowest, a mortal misery, or a miserable mortality; and the demons, who occupy the
mean, a miserable eternity, or an eternal misery. As to those five things which Apuleius
included in his definition of demons, he did not show, as he promised, that the demons are
mediate. For three of them, that their nature is animal, their mind rational, their soul
subject to passions, he said that they have in common with men; one thing, their eternity,
in common with the gods; and one proper to themselves, their aerial body. How, then, are
they intermediate, when they have three things in common with the lowest, and only one in
common with the highest? Who does not see that the intermediate position is abandoned in
proportion as they tend to, and are depressed towards, the lowest extreme? But perhaps we
are to accept them as intermediate because of their one property of an aerial body, as the
two extremes have each their proper body, the gods an ethereal men a terrestrial body, and
because two of the qualities they possess in common with man they possess also in common
with the gods, namely, their animal nature and rational mind. For Apuleius himself, in
speaking of gods and men, said, "You have two animal natures." And Platonists
are wont to ascribe a rational mind to the gods. Two qualities remain, their liability to
passion, and their eternity,--the first of which they have in common with men, the second
with the gods; so that they are neither wafted to the highest nor depressed to the lowest
extreme, but perfectly poised in their intermediate position. But then, this is the very
circumstance which constitutes the eternal misery, or miserable eternity, of the demons.
For he who says that their soul is subject to passions would also have said that they are
miserable, had he not blushed for their worshippers. Moreover, as the world is governed,
not by fortuitous hap-hazard, but, as the Platonists themselves avow, by the providence of
the supreme God, the misery of the demons would not be eternal unless their wickedness
were great.
If, then, the blessed are rightly styled
eudemons, the demons intermediate between gods and men are not eudemons. What, then, is
the local position of those good demons, who, above men but beneath the gods, afford
assistance to the former, minister to the latter? For if they are good and eternal, they
are doubtless blessed. But eternal blessedness destroys their intermediate character,
giving them a close resemblance to the gods, and widely separating them from men. And
therefore the Platonists will in vain strive to show how the good demons, if they are both
immortal and blessed, can justly be said to hold a middle place between the gods, who are
immortal and blessed, and men, who are mortal and miserable. For if they have both
immortality and blessedness in common with the gods, and neither of these in common with
men, who are both miserable and mortal, are they not rather remote from men and united
with the gods, than intermediate between them. They would be intermediate if they held one
of their qualities in common with the one party, and the other with the other, as man is a
kind of mean between angels and beasts,--the beast being an irrational and mortal animal,
the angel a rational and immortal one, while man, inferior to the angel and superior to
the beast, and having in common with the one mortality, and with the other reason, is a
rational and mortal animal. So, when we seek for an intermediate between the blessed
immortals and miserable mortals, we should find a being which is either mortal and
blessed, or immortal and miserable.
CHAP. 14.--WHETHER MEN,
THOUGH MORTAL, CAN ENJOY TRUE BLESSEDNESS.
It is a great question among men, whether man can
be mortal and blessed. Some, taking the humbler view of his condition, have denied that he
is capable of blessedness so long as he continues in this mortal life; others, again, have
spurned this idea, and have been bold enough to maintain that, even though mortal, men may
be blessed by attaining wisdom. But if this be the case, why are not these wise men
constituted mediators between miserable mortals and the blessed immortals, since they have
blessedness in common with the latter, and mortality in common with the former? Certainly,
if they are blessed, they envy no one (for what more miserable than envy?), but seek with
all their might to help miserable mortals on to blessedness, so that after death they may
become immortal, and be associated with the blessed and immortal angels.
CHAP. 15.--OF THE MAN
CHRIST JESUS, THE MEDIATOR BETWEEN GOD AND MEN.
But if, as is much more probable and credible, it
must needs be that all men, so long as they are mortal, are also miserable, we must seek
an intermediate who is not only man, but also God, that, by the interposition of His
blessed mortality, He may bring men out of their mortal misery to a blessed immortality.
In this intermediate two things are requisite, that He become mortal, and that He do not
continue mortal. He did become mortal, not rendering the divinity of the Word infirm, but
assuming the infirmity of flesh. Neither did He continue mortal in the flesh, but raised
it from the dead; for it is the very fruit of His mediation that those, for the sake of
whose redemption He became the Mediator, should not abide eternally in bodily death.
Wherefore it became the Mediator between us and God to have both a transient mortality and
a permanent blessedness, that by that which is transient He might be assimilated to
mortals, and might translate them from mortality to that which is permanent. Good angels,
therefore, cannot mediate between miserable mortals and blessed immortals, for they
themselves also are both blessed and immortal; but evil angels can mediate, because they
are immortal like the one party, miserable like the other. To these is opposed the good
Mediator, who, in opposition to their immortality and misery, has chosen to be mortal for
a time, and has been able to continue blessed in eternity. It is thus He has destroyed, by
the humility of His death and the benignity of His blessedness, those proud immortals and
hurtful wretches, and has prevented them from seducing to misery by their boast of
immortality those men whose hearts He has cleansed by faith, and whom He has thus freed
from their impure dominion.
Man, then, mortal and miserable, and far removed
from the immortal and the blessed, what medium shall he choose by which he may be united
to immortality and blessedness? The immortality of the demons, which might have some charm
for man, is miserable; the mortality of Christ, which might offend man, exists no longer.
In the one there is the fear of an eternal misery; in the other, death, which could not be
eternal, can no longer be feared, and blessedness, which is eternal, must be loved. For
the immortal and miserable mediator interposes himself to prevent us from passing to a
blessed immortality, because that which hinders such a passage, namely, misery, continues
in him; but the mortal and blessed Mediator interposed Himself, in order that, having
passed through mortality, He might of mortals make immortals (showing His power to do this
in His own resurrection), and from being miserable to raise them to the blessed company
from the number of whom He had Himself never departed. There is, then, a wicked mediator,
who separates friends, and a good Mediator, who reconciles enemies. And those who separate
are numerous, because the multitude of the blessed are blessed only by their participation
in the one God; of which participation the evil angels being deprived, they are wretched,
and interpose to hinder rather than to help to this blessedness, and by their very number
prevent us from reaching that one beatific good, to obtain which we need not many but one
Mediator, the uncreated Word of God, by whom all things were made, and in partaking of
whom we are blessed. I do not say that He is Mediator because He is the Word, for as the
Word He is supremely blessed and supremely immortal, and therefore far from miserable
mortals; but He is Mediator as He is man, for by His humanity He shows us that, in order
to obtain that blessed and beatific good, we need not seek other mediators to lead us
through the successive steps of this attainment, but that the blessed and beatific God,
having Himself become a partaker of our humanity, has afforded us ready access to the
participation of His divinity. For in delivering us from our mortality and misery, He does
not lead us to the immortal and blessed angels, so that we should become immortal and
blessed by participating in their nature, but He leads us straight to that Trinity, by
participating in which the angels themselves are blessed. Therefore, when He chose to be
in the form of a servant, and lower than the angels, that He might be our Mediator, He
remained higher than the angels, in the form of God,--Himself at once the way of life on
earth and life itself in heaven.
CHAP. 16.--WHETHER IT IS
REASONABLE IN THE PLATONISTS TO DETERMINE THAT THE CELESTIAL GODS DECLINE CONTACT WITH
EARTHLY THINGS AND INTERCOURSE WITH MEN, WHO THEREFORE REQUIRE THE INTERCESSION OF THE
DEMONS.
That opinion, which the same Platonist avers that
Plato uttered, is not true, "that no god holds intercourse with men." And
this, he says, is the chief evidence of their exaltation, that they are never contaminated
by contact with men. He admits, therefore, that the demons are contaminated; and it
follows that they cannot cleanse those by whom they are themselves contaminated, and thus
all alike become impure, the demons by associating with men, and men by worshipping the
demons. Or, if they say that the demons are not contaminated by associating and dealing
with men, then they are better than the gods, for the gods, were they to do so, would be
contaminated. Four this, we are told, is the glory of the gods, that they are so highly
exalted that no human intercourse can sully them. He affirms, indeed, that the supreme
God, the Creator of all things, whom we call the true God, is spoken of by Plato as the
only God whom the poverty of human speech fails even passably to describe; and that even
the wise, when their mental energy is as far as possible delivered from the trammels of
connection with the body, have only such gleams of insight into His nature as may be
compared to a flash of lightning illumining the darkness. If, then, this supreme God, who
is truly exalted above all things, does nevertheless visit the minds of the wise, when
emancipated from the body, with an intelligible and ineffable presence, though this be
only occasional, and as it were a swift flash of athwart the darkness, why are the other
gods so sublimely removed from all contact with men, as if they would be polluted by it?
as if it were not a sufficient refutation of this to lift up our eyes to those heavenly
bodies which give the earth its needful light. If the stars, though they, by his account,
are visible gods, are not contaminated when we look at them, neither are the demons
contaminated when men see them quite closely. But perhaps it is the human voice, and not
the eye, which pollutes the gods; and therefore the demons are appointed to mediate and
carry men's utterances to the gods, who keep themselves remote through fear of pollution?
What am I to say of the other senses? For by smell neither the demons, who are present,
nor the gods, though they were present and inhaling the exhalations of living men, would
be polluted if they are not contaminated with the effluvia of the carcasses offered in
sacrifice. As for taste, they are pressed by no necessity of repairing bodily decay, so as
to be reduced to ask food from men. And touch is in their own power. For while it may seem
that contact is so called, because the sense of touch is specially concerned in it, yet
the gods, if so minded, might mingle with men, so as to see and be seen, hear and be
heard; and where is the need of touching? For men would not dare to desire this, if
they were favored with the sight or conversation of gods or good demons; and if through
excessive curiosity they should desire it, how could they accomplish their wish without
the consent of the god or demon, when they cannot touch so much as a sparrow unless it be
caged?
There is, then, nothing to hinder the gods from
mingling in a bodily form with men, from seeing and being seen, from speaking and hearing.
And if the demons do thus mix with men, as I said, and are not polluted, while the gods,
were they to do so, should be polluted, then the demons are less liable to pollution than
the gods. And if even the demons are contaminated, how can they help men to attain
blessedness after death, if, so far from being able to cleanse them, and present them
clean to the unpolluted gods, these mediators are themselves polluted? And if they cannot
confer this benefit on men, what good can their friendly mediation do? Or shall its result
be, not that men find entrance to the gods, but that men and demons abide together in a
state of pollution, and consequently of exclusion from blessedness? Unless, perhaps, some
one may say that, like sponges or things of that sort, the demons themselves, in the
process of cleansing their friends, become themselves the filthier in proportion as the
others become clean. But if this is the solution, then the gods, who shun contact or
intercourse with men for fear of pollution, mix with demons who are far more polluted. Or
perhaps the gods, who cannot cleanse men without polluting themselves, can without
pollution cleanse the demons who have been contaminated by human contact? Who can believe
such follies, unless the demons have practised their deceit upon him? If seeing and being
seen is contamination, and if the gods, whom Apuleius himself calls visible, "the
brilliant lights of the world," and the other stars, are seen by men, are we to
believe that the demons, who cannot be seen unless they please, are safer from
contamination? Or if it is only the seeing and not the being seen which contaminates, then
they must deny that these gods of theirs, these brilliant lights of the world, see men
when their rays beam upon the earth. Their rays are not contaminated by lighting on all
manner of pollution, and are we to suppose that the gods would be contaminated if they
mixed with men, and even if contact were needed in order to assist them? For there is
contact between the earth and the sun's or moon's rays, and yet this does not pollute the
light.
CHAP. 17.--THAT TO OBTAIN THE BLESSED LIFE, WHICH
CONSISTS IN PARTAKING OF THE SUPREME GOOD, MAN NEEDS SUCH MEDIATION AS IS FURNISHED NOT BY
A DEMON, BUT BY CHRIST ALONE.
I am considerably surprised that such learned
men, men who pronounce all material and sensible things to be altogether inferior to those
that are spiritual and intelligible, should mention bodily contact in connection with the
blessed life. Is that sentiment of Plotinus forgotten?--"We must fly to our beloved
fatherland. There is the Father, there our all. What fleet or flight shall convey us
thither? Our way is, to become like God." If, then, one is nearer to God the liker
he is to Him, there is no other distance from God than unlikeness to Him. And the soul of
man is unlike that incorporeal and unchangeable and eternal essence, in proportion as it
craves things temporal and mutable. And as the things beneath, which are mortal and
impure, cannot hold intercourse with the immortal purity which is above, a mediator is
indeed needed to remove this difficulty; but not a mediator who resembles the highest
order of being by possessing an immortal body, and the lowest by having a diseased soul,
which makes him rather grudge that we be healed than help our cure. We need a Mediator
who, being united to us here below by the mortality of His body, should at the same time
be able to afford us truly divine help in cleansing and liberating us by means of the
immortal righteousness of His spirit, whereby He remained heavenly even while here upon
earth. Far be it from the incontaminable God to fear pollution from the man He assumed,
or from the men among whom He lived in the form of a man. For, though His incarnation
showed us nothing else, these two wholesome facts were enough, that true divinity cannot
be polluted by flesh, and that demons are not to be considered better than ourselves
because they have not flesh. This, then, as Scripture says, is the "Mediator
between God and man, the man Christ Jesus," of whose divinity, whereby He is equal
to the Father, and humanity, whereby He has become like us, this is not the place to speak
as fully as I could.
CHAP. 18.--THAT THE
DECEITFUL DEMONS, WHILE PROMISING TO CONDUCT MEN TO GOD BY THEIR INTERCESSION, MEAN TO
TURN THEM FROM THE PATH OF TRUTH.
As to the demons, these false and deceitful
mediators, who, though their uncleanness of spirit frequently reveals their misery and
malignity, yet, by virtue of the levity of their aerial bodies and the nature of the
places they inhabit, do contrive to turn us aside and hinder our spiritual progress; they
do not help us towards God, but rather prevent us from reaching Him. Since even in the
bodily way, which is erroneous and misleading, and in which righteousness does not
walk,--for we must rise to God not by bodily ascent, but by incorporeal or spiritual
conformity to Him,--in this bodily way, I say, which the friends of the demons arrange
according to the weight of the various elements, the aerial demons being set between the
ethereal gods and earthy men, they imagine the gods to have this privilege, that by this
local interval they are preserved from the pollution of human contact. Thus they believe
that the demons are contaminated by men rather than men cleansed by the demons, and that
the gods themselves should be polluted unless their local superiority pserved them. Who
is so wretched a creature as to expect purification by a way in which men are
contaminating, demons contaminated, and gods contaminable? Who would not rather choose
that way whereby we escape the contamination of the demons, and are cleansed from
pollution by the incontaminable God, so as to be associated with the uncontaminated
angels?
CHAP. 19.--THAT EVEN
AMONG THEIR OWN WORSHIPPERS THE NAME "DEMON" HAS NEVER A GOOD SIGNIFICATION.
But as some of these demonolators, as I may call
them, and among them Labeo, allege that those whom they call demons are by others called
angels, I must, if I would not seem to dispute merely about words, say something about the
good angels. The Platonists do not deny their existence, but prefer to call them good
demons. But we, following Scripture, according to which we are Christians, have learned
that some of the angels are good, some bad, but never have we read in Scripture of good
demons; but wherever this or any cognate term occurs, it is applied only to wicked
spirits. And this usage has become so universal, that, even among those who are called
pagans, and who maintain that demons as well as gods should be worshipped, there is
scarcely a man, no matter how well read and learned, who would dare to say by way of
praise to his slave, You have a demon, or who could doubt that the man to whom he said
this would consider it a curse? Why, then, are we to subject ourselves to the necessity of
explaining away what we have said when we have given offence by using the word demon, with
which every one, or almost every one, connects a bad meaning, while we can so easily evade
this necessity by using the word angel?
CHAP. 20.--OF THE KIND
OF KNOWLEDGE WHICH PUFFS UP THE DEMONS.
However, the very origin of the name suggests
something worthy of consideration, if we compare it with the divine books. They are called
demons from a Greek word meaning knowledge. Now the apostle, speaking with the Holy
Spirit, says, "Knowledge puffeth up, but charity buildeth up." And this can
only be understood as meaning that without charity knowledge does no good, but inflates a
man or magnifies him with an empty windiness. The demons, then, have knowledge without
charity, and are thereby so inflated or proud, that they crave those divine honors and
religious services which they know to be due to the true God, and still, as far as they
can, exact these from all over whom they have influence. Against this pride of the demons,
under which the human race was held subject as its merited punishment, there was exerted
the mighty influence of the humility of God, who appeared in the form of a servant; but
men, resembling the demons in pride, but not in knowledge, and being puffed up with
uncleanness, failed to recognize Him.
CHAP. 21.--TO WHAT
EXTENT THE LORD WAS PLEASED TO MAKE HIMSELF KNOWN TO THE DEMONS.
The devils themselves knew this manifestation of
God so well, that they said to the Lord though clothed with the infirmity of flesh,
"What have we to do with Thee, Jesus of Nazareth? Art Thou come to destroy us before
the time?" From these words, it is clear that they had great knowledge, and no
charity. They feared His power to punish, and did not love His righteousness. He made
known to them so much as He pleased, and He was pleased to make known so much as was
needful. But He made Himself known not as to the holy angels, who know Him as the Word of
God, and rejoice in His eternity, which they partake, but as was requisite to strike with
rror the beings from whose tyranny He was going to free those who were predestined to
His kingdom and the glory of it, eternally true and truly eternal. He made Himself known,
therefore, to the demons, not by that which is life eternal, and the unchangeable light
which illumines the pious, whose souls are cleansed by the faith that is in Him, but by
some temporal effects of His power, and evidences of His mysterious presence, which were
more easily discerned by the angelic senses even of wicked spirits than by human
infirmity. But when He judged it advisable gradually to suppress these signs, and to
retire into deeper obscurity, the prince of the demons doubted whether He were the Christ,
and endeavored to ascertain this by tempting Him, in so far as He permitted Himself to be
tempted, that He might adapt the manhood He wore to be an example for our imitation. But
after that temptation, when, as Scripture says, He was ministered to by the angels who
are good and holy, and therefore objects of terror to the impure spirits, He revealed more
and more distinctly to the demons how great He was, so that, even though the infirmity of
His flesh might seem contemptible, none dared to resist His authority.
CHAP. 22.--THE
DIFFERENCE BETWEEN THE KNOWLEDGE OF THE HOLY ANGELS AND THAT OF THE DEMONS.
The good angels, therefore, hold cheap all that
knowledge of material and transitory things which the demons are so proud of
possessing,--not that they are ignorant of these things, but because the love of God,
whereby they are sanctified, is very dear to them, and because, in comparison of that not
merely immaterial but also unchangeable and ineffable beauty, with the holy love of which
they are inflamed, they despise all things which are beneath it, and all that is not it,
that they may with every good thing that is in them enjoy that good which is the source of
their goodness. And therefore they have a more certain knowledge even of those temporal
and mutable things, because they contemplate their principles and causes in the word of
God, by which the world was made,--those causes by which one thing is, approved, another
rejected, and all arranged. But the demons do not behold in the wisdom of God these
eternal, and, as it were, cardinal causes of things temporal, but only foresee a larger
part of the future than men do, by reason of their greater acquaintance with the signs
which are hidden from us. Sometimes, too, it is their own intentions they predict. And,
finally, the demons are frequently, the angels never, deceived. For it is one thing, by
the aid of things temporal and changeable, to conjecture the changes that may occur in
time, and to modify such things by one's own will and faculty,--and this is to a certain
extent permitted to the demons,--it is another thing to foresee the changes of times in
the eternal and immutable laws of God, which live in His wisdom, and to know the will of
God, the most infallible and powerful of all causes, by participating in His spirit; and
this is granted to the holy angels by a just discretion. And thus they are not only
eternal, but blessed. And the good wherein they are blessed is God, by whom they were
created. For without end they enjoy the contemplation and participation of Him.
CHAP. 23.--THAT THE NAME OF GODS IS FALSELY GIVEN
TO THE GODS OF THE GENTILES, THOUGH SCRIPTURE APPLIES IT BOTH TO THE HOLY ANGELS AND JUST
MEN.
If the Platonists prefer to call these angels
gods rather than demons, and to reckon them with those whom Plato, their founder and
master, maintains were created by the supreme God, they are welcome to do so, for I
will not spend strength in fighting about words. For if they say that these beings are
immortal, and yet created by the supreme God, blessed but by cleaving to their Creator and
not by their own power, they say what we say, whatever name they call these beings by. And
that this is the opinion either of all or the best of the Platonists can be ascertained by
their writings. And regarding the name itself, if they see fit to call such blessed and
immortal creatures gods, this need not give rise to any serious discussion between us,
since in our own Scriptures we read, "The God of gods, the Lord hath spoken;"
and again, "Confess to the God of gods;" and again, "He is a great King
above all gods." And where it is said, "He is to be feared above all
gods," the reason is forthwith added, for it follows, "for all the gods of the
nations are idols, but the Lord made the heavens." He said, "above all
gods," but added, "of the nations;" that is to say, above all those whom
the nations count gods, in other words, demons. By them He is to be feared with that
terror in which they cried to the Lord, "Hast Thou come to destroy us?" But
where it is said, "the God of gods," it cannot be understood as the god of the
demons; and far be it from us to say that "great King above all gods" means
"great King above all demons." But the same Scripture also calls men who belong
to God's people" gods:" "I have said, Ye are gods, and all of you children
of the Most High." Accordingly, when God is styled God of gods, this may be
understood of these gods; and so, too, when He is styled a great King above all gods.
Nevertheless, some one may say, if men are called
gods because they belong to God's people, whom He addresses by means of men and angels,
are not the immortals, who already enjoy that felicity which men seek to attain by
worshipping God, much more worthy of the title? And what shall we reply to this, if not
that it is not without reason that in holy Scripture men are more expressly styled gods
than those immortal and blessed spirits to whom we hope to be equal in the resurrection,
because there was a fear that the weakness of unbelief, being overcome with the excellence
of these beings, might presume to constitute some of them a god? In the case of men this
was a result that need not be guarded against. Besides, it was right that the men
belonging to God's people should be more expressly called gods, to assure and certify them
that He who is called God of gods is their God; because, although those immortal and
blessed spirits who dwell in the heavens are called gods, yet they are not called gods of
gods, that is to say, gods of the men who constitute God's people, and to whom it is said,
"I have said. Ye are gods, and all of you the children of the Most High." Hence
the saying of the apostle, "Though there be that are called gods, whether in heaven
or in earth, as there be gods many and lords many, but to us there is but one God, the
Father, of whom are all things, and we in Him; and one Lord Jesus Christ, by whom are all
things, and we by Him."
We need not, therefore, laboriously contend about
the name, since the reality is so obvious as to admit of no shadow of doubt. That which we
say, that the angels who are sent to announce the will of God to men belong to the order
of blessed immortals, does not satisfy the Platonists, because they believe that this
ministry is discharged, not by those whom they call gods, in other words, not by blessed
immortals, but by demons, whom they dare not affirm to be blessed, but only immortal, or
if they do rank them among the blessed immortals, yet only as good demons, and not as gods
who dwell in the heaven of heavens remote from all human contact. But, though it may seem
mere wrangling about a name, yet the name of demon is so detestable that we cannot bear in
any sense to apply it to the holy angels. Now, therefore, let us close this book in the
assurance that, whatever we call these immortal and blessed spirits, who yet are only
creatures, they do not act as mediators to introduce to everlasting felicity miserable
mortals, from whom they are severed by a twofold distinction. And those others who are
mediators, in so far as they have immortality in common with their superiors, and misery
in common with their inferiors (for they are justly miserable in punishment of their
wickedness), cannot bestow upon us, but rather grudge that we should possess, the
blessedness from which they themselves are excluded. And so the friends of the demons have
nothing considerable to allege why we should rather worship them as our helpers than avoid
them as traitors to our interests. As for those spirits who are good, and who are
therefore not only immortal but also blessed, and to whom they suppose we, should give the
title of gods, and offer worship and sacrifices for the sake of inheriting a future life,
we shall, by God's help, endeavor in the following book to show that these spirits, call
them by what name, and ascribe to them what nature you will, desire that religious worship
be paid to God alone, by whom they were created, and by whose communications of Himself to
them they are blessed.
BOOK TEN
TABLE OF CONTENTS
|